Monday 22 April 2024

How Objects Conform to Knowing

 A short paper to commemorate Kant’s 300th birthday

 "How Objects Conform to Knowing: Kant’s Example of a Line"

Marco Bettoni

1. Introduction

How do we know something in space, for instance a line? In 1787, at the core of his theory of knowledge, Kant mentions an example which answers this question in the following way (B 138) [1]:

To know anything in space, for instance, a line, I must draw it”
(original: «Um aber irgend etwas im Raume zu erkennen, z.B. eine Linie, muss ich sie ziehen“).

In other words, in order to know (see, feel) a line in space I must do something (for example look in a certain way) or, more precisely, I must perform certain mental operations, call them “line operations”. We will see later that by "I must draw it" Kant does not refer to a physical line in space affecting our sense organs but only to a mental act.This means that even if there is no physical line involved, whenever I perform those line operations, then as a result, I will know a line. By performing “line operations” in space we obtain as a result lines, we know lines. This means that the relation between objects and knowing is of the kind result-to-operation (Fig. 1).  

Fig. 1 The relationship between objects and knowing

Look now at Figure 2: the white circles on a black background represent schematically stars in the night sky. There are no drawn (physical) lines, but according to Kant’s example, you could nonetheless be able to know (see) some line: how?

 

Fig. 2 The night sky (Ceccato 1980; Parini 1996)

If what we know in space depends on what we do, on the mental operations we perform, then, in the case of vision, what happens is that what we see depends on how we look. We can of course see Figure 2 as “chaos” but also see in it an ordered set of straight (Figure 3) or circular lines (Figure 4). And many other different ordered ways of looking at Figure 2 are possible (spiral lines, combined spiral and linear lines, etc.).

                      

Fig. 3 Straight lines that                                             Fig. 4 Circular lines that
can be seen in Fig. 2                                                  can be seen in Fig. 2

2. Fundamental question and answer

    In a famous letter to his friend Markus Herz (21.2.1772) Kant wrote that he was planning to publish a work in which he wanted to answer the question:

«on which ground is founded the relation between what we call 'Vorstellung' [knowledge unit, knowing] in us and the object»auf welchem Grunde beruhet die Beziehung desjenigen, was man in uns Vorstellung nennt, auf den Gegenstand»).

Fifteen years later, in the second edition of his main work, the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant presents the answer to that question as the central hypothesis of his theory by saying that objects must conform to our knowing [2]. He also emphasizes that this "revolution" (so-called Copernican Revoltuion) constitutes the main purpose of the Critique (BXXII).

Fig. 5 Kant’s Copernican Revolution

In order to understand Kant's "Copernican Revolution" (objects must conform to our knowing) and its consequences for epistemology in 2024, the real challenge lies in a critical reflection upon the specific components of Kant's hypothesis, which amounts at asking 3 crucial questions:

  1. What is Kant's conception of "object"?
  2.  What is Kant's conception of "must conform to"?
  3.  What is Kant's conception of "(faculty of) knowing"?

3. How a line conforms to our knowing

The basis for answering these 3 questions can be found in the Analytic of Concepts (Kant, B90 to B 169). As an example, consider, in the Deduction, Kant's summarized explanation of his hypothesis in the crucial § 17 in the B edition of the Critique [3] (B137, my translation based on Kemp-Smith):

“Understanding is, to use general terms, the faculty of knowledge.  This knowledge consists in the determinate relation of given knowledge units to an object; and an object is that in the concept of which the manifold of a given intuition is united. Now all unification of knowledge units demands in fact unity of consciousness in the synthesis of them.”

The mechanism described in this passage is that of "Vereinigung" (unification) of what we call "Vorstellungen" (knowledge units). Kant specifies further that this unification mechanism should act when "Vorstellungen" are synthesized ("in der Synthesis") and that the result of its operation is an (experiential) object. From this I conclude that this description could be clearly interpreted as an operational explanation (a proposition of a generative mechanism, Maturana 1988) of the totally new conception of "object" that Kant needs in order to articulate his Copernican Revolution.

Tightly related to that explanation, a few lines further Kant gives the previously mentioned example of a line, one of his most famous (and rare) examples [4] (B138, translation Kemp Smith):

„To know anything in space (for instance, a line), I must draw it, and thus synthetically bring into being a determinate combination of the given manifold, so that the unity of this act is at the same time the unity of consciousness (as in the concept of a line); and it is through this unity of consciousness that an object (a determinate space) is first known. “

Here Kant wants to explain how we know a "line" and if we look at the functional side of what he writes we see that he presents an operational explanation. In fact, Kant describes here a "line mechanism" that, if you let it operate in your mind, gives you as result of your mental operations that "line" that he wants to explain.

What is exemplified here for the case of a line is also paradigmatically valid for any acquired experience-independent knowledge unit (a priori concepts like begin, end, singular, plural, unit, element, part, whole, space, time, number, here, there, now, etc.): we should try to develop also for them generative mechanisms which, if we let them operate in our mind, would deliver the acquired a priori concept that we want to explain.

4 Kant’s A Priori is not innate

Finally, I would like to conclude this short paper to commemorate Kant’s 300th birthday with a remark on Kant’s conception of the apriori.

As Michael Oberhausen (1997) remarks: "To simply consider Kant's apriori as innate still is a widespread cliché". This cliché is being disseminated not only by contemporary philosophers - with whom Kant is known to be in contradiction - but also by scientists when they approach Kant's work.

Indeed, this is not astonishing if we consider that Kant's doctrine of the acquisition of experience-independent elements 'up to now has been quite ignored by research' (Oberhausen 1997, p. 6).

Fortunately, we have now Oberhausen's comprehensive study which supplies the proof that Kant's doctrine of the acquisition of a priori constructs ('Vorstellungen') is not of no or only of secondary relevance but "lies at the center of critical philosophy". In his summary Oberhausen emphasises that Kant "in many different places of his work again and again explicitly explained that both space and time as well as pure concepts are acquired ..." (Oberhausen 1997, p.6).

5 Conclusion

What are now the implications of such considerations for us in 2024?  I think that they can help to answer the crucial question of experience (learning): What do we contribute of our own to our knowledge?

In the light of Kant's explanations, the answer is that what we contribute of our own are the mechanisms and operations of acquisition, generalisation and application of acquired experience-independent elements ('reine Verstandesbegriffe a priori') that implement the unity of experience (categories) and are the conditions of possibility of experience.

Acknowledgments

I am very grateful to Kant for his life and for his work! His life is an example to me and his work gives me hope. Hope that we can find support in mastering the difficult task of making human beings out of ourselves, i.e. coming closer to the ideals of freedom, equality and fraternity than has been the case up to now.

That's why I'm so very grateful to Kant and why it has been my pleasure and duty to remind ourselves with a short text that we still urgently need Kant's philosophy in 2024.

Notes

Monday 1 January 2024

THE LADDER OF UNDERSTANDING

 MAKING BETTER SENSE OF WHAT WE EXPERIENCE
 
1. Homer (8th century BC), the poet who "has taught Greece" (Plato), shaped ancient Greek culture in terms of mythology.
 
2. Protagoras  (c. 490 BC – c. 420 BC) and the other sophists substitute the logos for the myth.
 
3. Socrates (c. 470–399 BC), through his methods of refutation and maieutics, leads from logos to aporia.
 
4. Aristotle (384–322 BC) begins the Metaphysics by surveying aporiai and develops from here his theoretical knowledge of the fundamental nature of reality.
 
5. Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) in his Critique of Pure Reason establishes the limits as to just how far reason may legitimately proceed.

6. Silvio Ceccato (1914-1997) developed operational methodology ("Metodologia Operativa") as a way that leads to operational mindfulness: the awareness of HOW WE KNOW.

------------------------------------------------------------------------------

How we act depends on how we understand what we experience (ourselves, society, the world, the universe, etc.). Mostly this understanding seems obvious to us, we do not feel the need to inquire into it. But then we cannot improve it! Fortunately wise men did that for us.

The "Ladder of Understanding" is a model of the steps that in the course of the centuries some wise men made for us in order to improve the human ability TO MAKE SENSE OF WHAT WE EXPERIENCE.

------------------------------------------------------------------------------

Thursday 3 November 2022

LTW - Stress and Mindfulness

 Living in Two Worlds - STRESS & MINDFULNESS

Fig.1 LTW Model of stress
L= individual Logical world; A = Attentional system; P = shared Physical world

Under conditions of stress negative emotions and negative feelings dominate the individual logical world L. The energy equilibrium is disrupted (see Fig.1): energy increases in L (diagram eL/t) and decreases in the attentional system A (diagram eA/t).

World L takes the lead and directs attention to negative memories (past) or negative visions (future). Attention becomes less autonomous, its activity is more than usual under the control of world L.

Under these conditions the attentional system cannot fulfill its task to connect world L and world P in an equilibrated way. Thus world L partially loses connection with the physical world P and the viability check is partially skipped.

This isolation of world L and its higher negative energy leads to a further increase of stress and this to a higher disconnection between world L and P.

This is where despair and psychological impairments find the needed environment to emerge and grow, for example obsessive thoughts and other aspects of OCD.

Fortunately the attentional system A can reestablish the lost energy equilibrium and reconnect world L and P.

How? Simple: by MINDFULNESS MEDITATION [1]. Simple, but not easy!

Mindfulness meditation increases the energy of the attentional system, reduces the dominance of world L and reestablishes the equilibrium and the connection between world L and world P. 

This is how,  seen from the perspective of the knowledge theory of Operational Constructivism, mindfulness meditation achieves its effect of reducing stress, pain and illness.

Notes:

[1] Kabat-Zinn, J. (1990) Full Catastrophe Living: Using the Wisdom of Your Body and Mind to Face Stress, Pain, and Illness. New York: Random House. Revised edition 2013.






Tuesday 2 August 2022

LTW - Emotions and feelings

 Living in Two Worlds - EMOTIONS & FEELINGS

This morning I woke up with the question: "where are emotions in the LTW model?". Good question, I thought ;-)

By the way, in terms of the LTW model, this question originated in the "passive thought" area:
==> it was not the result of a consciuos search for what may be missing in my model, nor the result of other active reflections.

My first idea for answering that question was to search for inspiration in some books I have in my library (see references). 

What I liked reading Luc Ciompi was the idea that every type of activity or experience contains emotional components as well as cognitive ones. What comes out as a result of the action or experience of an individual, are not simply cognitive but always more complex affective-cognitive structures [Ciompi, 1997, p. 47].

I further liked the definition by Antonio Damasio [1999, p. 50 ff], that emotions are complex patterns of bodily responses (biologically determined processes) as well as his distinction between emotions and feelings :
a) feeling = the private, mental experience of an emotion [Damasio 1999, p. 42]
b) emotion = the collection of chemical and neural responses (to an inducer), forming a pattern [Damasio 1999, p. 51]

What induces emotions? Regarding this topic I was not fully satisfied with the explanation given by Damasio [1999, p.56 ff]. The view proposed by Richard Lazarus seems to me more clear [Wikipedia 2022]. Lazarus considers that the inducer is a  "cognitive appraisal": the individual assesses an event or object cognitively, and this induces an emotion.

But I agree with Damasio that the inducers are shaped by development (different individuals) and culture (different societies): they shape what constitutes an inducer and they shape the expression of an emotion [Damasio 1999, p. 57].

The sequence of events which constitute an emotion (see Scherer's Component Process Model, [Scherer 2005]) can be represented in my LTW model as follows (see the event numbers in square brackets here and in Figure 1):

  • [1] cognitive appraisal: the assessment of an object or event happens in world 1, the logical world. It can happen both in its active side (conscious) or in its passive side (nonconscious). 
  • [2] bodily symptoms and expression: the appraisal induces some biological changes in the body (such as increased heart rate, pituitary adrenal response, etc.). The facial and vocal expression may change. The body is part of world 2, the shared physical world. 
  • [3] As next the individual can sense the emotion 
  • [4] As next the attentional system elaborates the emotion at mental level = the individual has a feeling (conscious or nonconscious) 
  • [5] Finally the individual may choose to react and how.

References:

  • Ciompi, L. 1997. Die emotionalen Grundlagen des Denkens. Entwurf einer fraktalen Affektlogik. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht 
  • Damasio, A. 1999. The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness, San Diego: Harcourt. 
  • Scherer, K.R. (2005). "What are emotions? And how can they be measured?". Social Science Information. 44 (4): 693–727. 
  • Wikipedia, 2022. Emotion. Section: Cognitive Theories https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Emotion#Cognitive_theories





Monday 1 August 2022

LTW - Attentional subsystems

 Living in Two Worlds - ATTENTIONAL subsystems

  1. The integration of the two worlds in which we live into one single world is the product of a functional system of our brain: an ATTENTIONAL system (Ceccato's model)

  2. ATTENTION, conceived as a system that we can control (cybernetic system), is the system that we use:
    a) to control the shared PHYSICAL world
    b) to construct our individual LOGICAL world
     
  3. In the attentional system we can distinguish 4 subsystems:
    a) SENSORY subsystem and MOTOR subsystem that enable us to control the shared PHYSICAL world by coordinating sensory experiences (seeing, hearing) with motor actions (reaching, touching).
    b) SCHEMA system and EQUILIBRATION system by which we construct our individual LOGICAL world (see next)
     
  4. These four subsystems are under the control of the attentionl system (core system)

  5. The SCHEMA system includes the functions of
    a) schematisation: for constructing mental constructs by means of action schemata (see Piaget)
    b) assimilation (Piaget): for fitting new mental constructs into existing cognitive structures (networks of mental constructs)
     
  6. The EQUILIBRATION system includes the functions of
    a) evaluation: for assessing the consistency of our cognitive structures
    b) accomodation (Piaget): for adapting existing cognitive structures to new mental constructs, when there are inconsistencies, contradicitions etc.



Friday 29 July 2022

How do we know - the HOW

 HOW DO WE KNOW? – the HOW

Fig. 1 Peek-a-boo is a prime example of an object permanence test (Wikipedia, image by Cynthia-Griggs)

A friend asked me about my LTW project, what is it about?

I answered - like in the LTW onepager - that this project is about the question “how do we know?” … and I was surprised to notice that this question seemed unclear to her.

But in fact, it is not surprising at all. It is easy to think, for example, that knowledge comes from learning, from perception, etc.; then the answer to “how do we know?” would be “by learning”, “by perceiving”, etc. and this would seem so clear, that many people, like my friend, would not see why we need a project for answering that question.

As a consequence, the LTW project needs to start by explaining its leading question “How do we know?”

In this question the [How] is not about procedures (perceiving, learning, etc.) but about the mechanisms (functions, operations) of knowing which enable such procedures.

So the question is not “[By which procedures] do we know?” but “[By which mechanisms (functions, operations)] do we know?"

An example can be taken from Jean Piaget: object permanence. The child develops the ability to understand (to know), that when an object is covered by a blanked, it has not finished to exist. The object still exists, there, under the blanket.

Step by step this develops into the “understanding that objects exist and events occur in the world independently of one's own actions” (1).

This ability is a mechanism of knowing that the child acquires and it answers the question “How do we know?” in relation to the specific case of objects that suddenly disappear from our sight.

Notes:

(1) McLeod 2021, Object Permanence, https://www.simplypsychology.org/Object-Permanence.html

Wednesday 27 July 2022

Two-worlds model - detailed diagram

 TWO-WORLDS MODEL - detailed diagram

This diagram of the Two Worlds Model is more detailed: it presents WORLD 2, the individual LOGICAL world (experiential world) with the distinction of two main areas of thinking, ACTIVE & PASSIVE processes.

The elements combined in this diagram have been previously described, see:

14.07.2022 HOW WE KNOW: A TWO-WORLDS MODEL
http://marco-bettoni.blogspot.com/2022/07/two-worlds-model-v2.html
 

16.07.2022 HOW WE KNOW: ACTIVE & PASSIVE PROCESSES
http://marco-bettoni.blogspot.com/2022/07/active-and-passive-thought.html